Selasa, Maret 07, 2017

Review Article

Edit Posted by with 7 comments
Assalamua’laikum wr.wb
Today, Puze will post about review article, This is my first time to review a article, hope you enjoy …

REVIEW ARTICLE
The History and Prehistory
of Natural Language Semantics1
Daniel Harris | Hunter College, CUNY

Identitas

I reviews article about the history and Prehistory of natural language semantics, post by Daniel Harris from Hunter College, CUNY. The article “The History and Prehistory of Natural Language Semantics” edited by Sandra Lapointe and Chris Pincock for Palgrave Macmillan in January 2015 at McMaster University. This article have 41 pages and this review is my responsibility, Dela Puzebang, ID: 1588203003.

Abstract

This Article was made to know the definitions of semantics according to many expert. We also know, the debates of many expert opinion from the article it could be wrong, because the author of this article was made a comparison for many opinions there. Explanation by the author and example, is used as methode. Expert opinions also are used to make the explanation of author stronger.

 For the result, by the explanations, examples, comparison with all expert’s methodologies and many expert’s opinion, the author conclude that the role of truth-condition idealization in the early history of natural-language semantics embodied a confusion. One that resulted from an insufficiently critical adoption of the methodology of prehistoric figures, including Frege, Tarski, and Carnap. What fascinates me about this confusion is that Frege, Tarski, and Carnap themselves did not suffer from it, and this is because they understood the nature of the truth-conditional idealization, its purposes, and its limitations.
                                                          
Introductory

The author began about the assumption of the meaning a sentence could be modeled by a single truth-condition, or by an entity with a truth-condition. The history of natural language semantics comes from Donald Davidson and Richard Montague, it began with a methodological Frege, Tarski, Carnap, and others had created to better understand artificial languages. For them, the study of linguistic meaning was follow the othe explanatory goals in logic, philosophy, and the foundations of mathematics, they get idealized from all aspect of meaning by one to one correspondence between sentences and truth-conditions. Davidson and Montague adopted the methodological by Frege, Tarski, Carnap and others about their idealization from truth-condition semantic phenomena. Lifting the truth-conditional idealization has forced semanticists to the conception of linguistic meaning that was originally by their methodology.

1.   Truth-Conditional Semantics and The Communicative Turn

The most fundamental way of dividing up approaches to linguistic meaning is on the basis of how they answer a question best articulated by David Lewis.
In order to say what a meaning is, we may first ask what a meaning does, and then find something that does that (1970: 193) “.

Meaning is a theoretical posit, and so our theory of it has to be grounded in the
explanatory role. Lewis’s question is the one raised by his methodological advice: what is the explanatory role of linguistic meaning? If I guess, the answer is the theory of Donald Davidson and Richard Montague. Lewis’s own answer to his question was that the meaning of a sentence “is something that determines the conditions under which a sentence is true or false” (1970: 193). By his answer, we know that still have relation with methodological Frege, Tarski, Carnap and others that is dynamic semantics-pragmatics and work on non-truth-condition-centric and truth-condition is from linguistic meaning natural-language semantics. Versions of this answer dominated natural-language semantics from its contemporary beginnings in the work of Donald Davidson (1965, 1967a, 1970) and Richard Montague (1970a,b, 1973) until now.

If we use ‘truth-conditional semantics’ as a broad covering term for any theoretical approach that articulates or embodies a truth-condition-centric answer to Lewis’s question, then many debates about how to do semantics are disputes between different species of semanticists within the truth-conditional genus. For example: are sentences’ semantic values functions from possible worlds to truth-va, lues (Cresswell 1973; Lewis 1970, 1975; von Fintel & Heim 2011), functions from more elaborate indices to truth-values (e.g., Montague 1974; Brogaard 2012; Egan, Hawthorne, & Weather son 2005; Lasarsohn 2005; MacFarlane 2014; Richard 2004), sets of centered worlds (Lewis 1979b), sets of situations (Barwise & Perry 1983), structured complexes made up of objects and properties (Russell 1903, 1918; Soames 1987), structured complexes made up of abstract modes of presentation (Frege 1892a,b; Evans 1986; Zalta 1988), or structured entities of other kinds (King 2007; Soames 2010)? These debates have all taken place within truth-conditional semantics as author’s conceive of it. The defenders agree of each of these view is determine that the role of meaning’s sentences its truth-condition. But they disagree about the role of truth-conditional meanings.

Similar points can be made about the debates of Davidson and Lewis methodology or role. Davidson’s work represents both the beginning of the contemporary era of natural-language semantics and the beginning of its truth-conditional paradigm (1965, 1967a, 1970). In order to answer Lewis’s Question, however, Davidson would have had to interpret it somewhat differently than Lewis did, because Davidson explicitly rejected the idea that a sentence’s meaning is an entity to which it bears a semantic relation.

Truth-conditional semantics is an active research program, and most introductory
semantics textbooks still embody truth-conditional assumptions. But natural-language semantics is now experiencing a major shift away from the foundational assumption that defines its truth-conditional strain. The best-known moniker for this shift is ‘the dynamic turn’, which picks up on the rise of dynamic semantics and the dynamic-pragmatic environment that is increasingly presupposed by non-dynamic approaches to semantics. in that it includes several other moves away from truthconditional semantics and toward various versions of the idea that the meaning of an expression is its role in communication or conversation. For this reason, the author will call the shift is the communicative turn.

The communicative turn, as the author understand it, heterogenous proposals have been driven by a consistent collection of data arising from five kinds of linguistic phenomena: non-declarative clauses, context-sensitivity, presupposition, conventional implicature, and expressive meaning. Sentence that exhibit these phenomena have been found to require revisionary semantic treatments either because they cannot be understood in terms of truth-conditional meaning (but are still meaningful), or because understanding them requires positing supplemental dimensions of meaning beyond truth-conditional content.

A paradigmatic example involves non-declarative clauses, including interrogatives
(e.g. (1)) and imperatives (e.g. (2)).
(1.) Did Frege discover any important dance steps?
(2.) Give my dog a bath!

It seems to be a category mistake to call sentences like these true or false, and so to ascribe truth-conditions to them. Interrogatives are for asking questions and imperatives are for issuing directives. This pre-theoretic idea has been cashed out semantically by a variety of suggestions to the effect that clauses’ semantic values be identified with the types of speech acts for which they can be directly and literally used (Searle 1969; Alston 2000; Barker 2004; Harris 2014).

By far the most influential approaches to non-declaratives, and to non-truthconditional aspects of meaning in general, have been built around dynamic models of conversation of the kind first proposed by Robert Stalnaker (1976, 2014). Taking propositions to be sets of possible worlds, Stalnaker defines the context set of a conversation as the intersection of the propositions in the common ground—the set of worlds compatible the participants’ presuppositions.

A conversation consisting solely of utterances of declarative sentences can then be understood as a “joint inquiry” whose goal is to zero in on the way the world actually is by adding more information to the common ground through a series of assertions, thus shrinking the number of possibilities in the context set. These ideas—conversational context as a body of shared representations, speech acts as ways of updating these representations, and sentence meanings as the raw material for these updates—have been generalized in a wide variety of ways.

David Lewis (1976) conceives of conversational context as a scoreboard that keeps track of various facts about what’s happening in the conversation in much the same way that a baseball scoreboard keeps track of numerous facts about the current state of a game. The resulting theories are classified as versions of either dynamic semantics or dynamic pragmatics, depending on whether they posit semantic or pragmatic mechanisms by which context is updated (K. Lewis 2011, 2014).

The semantic value of an interrogative clause, on this view, is a function that takes some context as an input and outputs a context that differs only in that it contains a new question under discussion. In dynamic-pragmatic frameworks, clauses’ semantic values do not contain instructions for updating the context, but are instead model-theoretic objects of types that fit into different dimensions of the context, so that it is easy to offer a pragmatic explanation of how uttering a sentence with such a semantic value updates the context in the appropriate way (Portner 2004).

Model the issues that speakers want to resolve and which determine which speech acts are relevant (Roberts 1996/2012), as well as the to-do list, which tracks speakers’ practical commitments (Portner 2004). This is accomplished in either of two ways: in dynamic-semantic frameworks, the semantic value of a clause is its context-change potential—a function that maps possible states of the context to other possible states (e.g. Ciardelli, Groenendijk, & Roelofsen 2013; Starr ms).

The semantic value of an interrogative clause, on this view, is a function that takes some context as an input and outputs a context that differs only in that it contains a new question under discussion. In dynamic-pragmatic frameworks, clauses’ semantic values do not contain instructions for updating the context, but are instead model theoretic objects of types that fit into different dimensions of the context, so that it is easy to offer a pragmatic explanation of how uttering a sentence with such a semantic value updates the context in the appropriate way (Portner 2004).

Versions of expressivism have been defended by philosophers for decades, but the view has also recently made its way into mainstream semantic theory via the work of Alan Gibbard (1990, 2003) whose account of expressive meaning is built on top of Stalnaker’s theory of assertion. On Gibbard’s view, conversational contexts contain a practical dimension, which he models in terms of either normative systems (1990) or plans (2003), and the function of normative speech is to update this practical dimension of context in the same way that descriptive speech is used to update the context’s informational dimension.

2.   The Truth-Conditional Idealization

If you ask a present-day semanticist Lewis’s question—what does meaning do? The answer will increasingly be that it does many things, and that what unites all of the things meaning does is that they must be spelled out as part of a broader theory of conversation. If we accept, with growing ranks of semanticists, that the communicative turn in at least some of its manifestations constitutes progress.

Then rises the question phenomenon, why weren’t these phenomena attended to during the heyday of truth-conditional semantics? To answer these questions, we should look to the early-20th-Century work on logic, mathematics, and philosophy in the context of which the methodological toolkit of truth-conditional semantics took shape. If the contemporary history of semantics begins with a focus on natural language initiated by Davidson and Montague, its prehistory played out in the work of logicians, mathematicians, and philosophers who focused on formal languages and heavily idealized fragments of natural language. The author will focus on the three figures from the prehistory of contemporary semantics who have had the greatest influence on it: Frege, Tarski, and Carnap. To be sure, many other early-20th-Century philosophers and mathematicians laid important components of the foundation of truth-conditional semantics. But no early-20th-Century figure matches the influence , of the three he will discuss.

These are the same features of language and linguistic meaning that are currently driving the communicative turn: non-declarative clauses, expressive meaning, presupposition, conventional implicature, and context-sensitivity. Frege, Tarski,mand Carnap idealized away from these phenomena by limiting their attention to formalized languages made up of declarative, context insensitive sentences that possess a single, truth-conditional dimension of significance.

3.    The Pivot

The event that demarcates the history of contemporary semantics from its prehistory was a pivot from one diverse collection explanatory goals to a very different one. What went under the name ‘semantics’ prior to this pivot was a set of tools used to pursue logical, mathematical, and philosophical projects. The contemporary history of semantics began with a shift to the goal of empirically investigating natural language by showing how the semantic properties of sentences systematically depend on their structures and the semantic properties of their component expressions.

Among the central aims of Davidson’s influential early papers on semantics
were (a) to overcome Tarski’s skepticism about the possibility of applying his tools to the study of natural language, and (b) to argue that such an application of Tarski's tools could “do duty” as a theory of meaning for natural language (1967a,1970, 1973).  Davidson recognized that his proposals differed from Tarski’s in several key ways; since his goal was not to define truth in a formal language, but rather to use a primitive notion of truth to construct an axiomatic theory that could stand in as a theory of meaning, Davidson couldn’t take semantic notions such as the synonymy of object-language and metalanguage expressions for granted, as Tarski had. He marked this distinction subtly, by describing his project as 18 A brief history of this research program is told by Partee (2004: ch.1), who played a central role in establishing it, particularly among linguists.

In Weisberg’s helpful terminology, Frege, Tarski, and Carnap can best be construed as aiming at minimalist idealizations of the semantic properties they studied. Minimalist idealization is the practice of constructing and studying theoretical models that include only the core causal factors which give rise to a phenomenon. Such a representation is often called a minimal model of the phenomenon. Put more explicitly, a minimalist model contains only those factors that make a difference to the occurrence and essential character of the phenomenon in question. (2007: 642)

We might even hypothesize that since Lewis’s immediate goal in linking sentence meanings with truth conditions was to debunk the structuralist approach to semantics, which had been proposed by Katz & Postal (1964) and initially endorsed by Chomsky (1965), we should take Lewis’s broader point to have been that semantics involves the kind of word–world connections that are still embodied in its post-communicative-turn forms. Given these continuities, we might wonder, wherein lies the revolution?

Problems

2. The Truth-Conditional Idealization

The author trying to finish the problem of semantic with explanation based expert,
The basic misunderstanding is the identification of Frege's notion of Sinn (sense) with the notion of linguistic meaning. The misunderstanding is an easy one to fall into for two reasons. For one, the term “meaning” has always been vague, multi-purposed, and to some extent adaptive to the viewpoint of different theories. Pressing the term into service to characterize Frege's notion has seemed harmless enough, as long as it is made clear that the notion is restricted to an aspect of meaning relevant to fixing the truth value of sentences. 

A second reason for the misunderstanding has been that Frege did not lavish any considerable attention on the area in which the differences between sense and the ordinary notion of meaning are clearest—context dependent reference. Although the differences between meaning and sense are easiest to notice with indexicals (including proper names), the distinction issues from the fundamental cast of Frege’s work, a cast discernible throughout his career independently of issues about indexicals. Baldly put, Frege was primarily interested in the eternal structure of thought, of cognitive contents, not in conventional linguistic meaning. He pursued this interest by investigating the structure of language, and much of his work may be seen as directly relevant to theories of linguistic meaning. But the epistemic orientation of his theorizing leads to a notion of sense with a different theoretical function from modern notions of meaning (Burge 1979: 213).

3.The Pivot

We might even hypothesize that since Lewis’s immediate goal in linking sentence meanings with truth conditions was to debunk the structuralist approach to semantics, which had been proposed by Katz & Postal (1964) and initially endorsed by Chomsky (1965), we should take Lewis’s broader point to have been that semantics involves the kind of word–world connections that are still embodied in its post-communicative-turn forms. Given these continuities, we might wonder, wherein lies the revolution?

Methode

The author used to methodology of Davidson’s and Lewis’s work to finishing the problem.

Hasil

2. The Truth-Conditional Idealization
To answer that questions, we should look to the early-20th-Century work on logic, mathematics, and philosophy in the context of which the methodological toolkit of truth-conditional semantics took shape. If the contemporary history of semantics begins with a focus on natural language initiated by Davidson and Montague, its prehistory played out in the work of logicians, mathematicians, and philosophers who focused on formal languages and heavily idealized fragments of natural language. The author will focus on the three figures from the prehistory of contemporary semantics who have had the greatest influence on it: Frege, Tarski, and Carnap. To be sure, many other early-20th-Century philosophers and mathematicians laid important components of the foundation of truth-conditional semantics. But no early-20th-Century figure matches the influence , of the three he will discuss.

These are the same features of language and linguistic meaning that are currently driving the communicative turn: non-declarative clauses, expressive meaning, presupposition, conventional implicature, and context-sensitivity. Frege, Tarski,mand Carnap idealized away from these phenomena by limiting their attention to formalized languages made up of declarative, context insensitive sentences that possess a single, truth-conditional dimension of significance.


3.The Pivot
The answer, Author’s think, is that although the recent history of semantics may look from within like a series of gradual adjustments to a single, continuous modeltheoretic framework driven by an expanding collection of data, the framework that has resulted from these adjustments embodies a very different answer to one of the central foundational questions that semantics was originally designed to answer. What is linguistic meaning? The semantics of the 1979’s embodied and espoused a truth-condition-centric answer to this question; today’s semantics has turned to a communication-centric answer.

Moreover: the earlier answer to this question shaped semantic practice in ways that led to delayed progress and wrong turns on the ground, and so the issue is not of merely philosophical interest. I am therefore led to believe that the role of the truth-conditional idealization in the early history of natural-language semantics embodied a confusion—one that resulted from an insufficiently critical adoption of the methodology of prehistoric figures, including Frege, Tarski, and Carnap. What fascinates me about this confusion is that Frege, Tarski, and Carnap themselves did not suffer from it, and this is because they understood the nature of the truth-conditional idealization, its purposes, and its limitations.

By the article we know that frege’s theory or methodology is confusing. So, the author using other theory like Burge’s theory. Because, Frege’s theory interested in the eternal structure of thought, of cognitive contents, not in conventional linguistic meaning.

Conclusion

The author is finding the Frege’s theory can not use in semantic, because it is not in conventional linguistic meaning. Like Frege, Tarksi’s aim was not primarily to understand linguistic meaning and particularly not in natural language. He constructed and studied artificial languages and developed semantic tools to better understand those languages, but these pursuits were in the service of broader mathematical goals, including accounts of truth, definition, and logical consequence that were rigorous enough for mathematical use. As John Burgess puts it, “it was not linguistic understanding but mathematical fruitfulness that Tarski sought with his definition [of truth], and in this he was very successful” (2008: 154–5).


Analized

According the author on this article, some much question comes by the frege’s theory. Frege’s theory can not in semantic.

The Weakness

1.    The author did not give more example of the statement
2.    The author still using Frege’s theory eventhough it is wrong theory

The strength

1.    Perfect article, with all comparison in several statement,
2.    The authors know to makes a similarly in statement one expert to others.

Bibliography

-         Almog, Joseph, John Perry, and Howard Wettstein (). Themes from Kaplan
(Oxford University Press).
-         Alston, William P. (). Illocutionary Acts and Sentence Meaning. Cornell University
Press.
-         Asher, Nicholas, and Alex Lascarides. . Indirect Speech Acts. Synthese, (–
): –.
———. (): Logics of Conversation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Well, thank you somuch readers for coming in Puze’s blogger, …
See you guys J J